|
The Principle of Movement in the Structure of Islam
-Turning now to the groundwork of legal
principles in the Qur«n, it is perfectly clear that
far from leaving no scope for human thought and legislative activity
the intensive breadth of these principles virtually acts as an awakener
of human thought. Our early doctors of law taking their clue mainly
from this groundwork evolved a number of legal systems; and the
student of Muhammadan history knows very well that nearly half the
triumphs of Islam as a social and political power were due to the
legal acuteness of these doctors. Next to the Romans,
says von Kremer, there is no other nation besides the Arabs
which could call its own a system of law so carefully worked out.
But with all their comprehensiveness these systems are after all
individual interpretations, and as such cannot claim any finality.
I know the Ulem« of Islam claim finality for the popular
schools of Muhammadan Law, though they never found it possible to
deny the theoretical possibility of a complete Ijtih«d. I
have tried to explain the causes which, in my opinion, determined
this attitude of the Ulem«; but since things have changed
and the world of Islam is confronted and affected today by new forces
set free by the extraordinary development of human thought in all
its directions, I see no reason why this attitude should be maintained
any longer. Did the founders of our schools ever claim finality
for their reasonings and interpretations? Never. The claim of the
present generation of Muslim liberals to reinterpret the foundational
legal principles, in the light of their own experience and the altered
conditions of modern life is, in my opinion, perfectly justified.
The teaching of the Qur«n that life is a process of
progressive creation necessitates that each generation, guided but
unhampered by the work of its predecessors, should be permitted
to solve its own problems.
You will, I think, remind me here of the Turkish
poet Êiy« whom I quoted a moment ago, and ask whether
the equality of man and woman demanded by him, equality, that is
to say, in point of divorce, separation, and inheritance, is possible
according to Muhammadan Law. I do not know whether the awakening
of women in Turkey has created demands which cannot be met with
without a fresh interpretation of foundational principles. In the
Punjab, as everybody knows, there have been cases in which Muslim
women wishing to get rid of undesirable husbands have been driven
to apostasy. Nothing could be more distant from the aims of a missionary
religion. The Law of Islam, says the great Spanish jurist Im«m
Sh«tibâin his al-Muwafiq«t, aims at protecting
five things - Dân, Nafs, Aql, M«l, and Nasl. Applying
this test I venture to ask: Does the working of the rule relating
to apostasy, as laid down in the Hed«yah tend to protect the
interests of the Faith in this country? In view of the intense
conservatism of the Muslims of India, Indian judges cannot but stick
to what are called standard works. The result is that while the
peoples are moving the law remains stationary.
With regard to the Turkish poets demand, I
am afraid he does not seem to know much about the family law of
Islam. Nor does he seem to understand the economic significance
of the Quranic rule of inheritance. Marriage, according to Muhammadan
Law, is a civil contract. The wife at the time of marriage is at
liberty to get the husbands power of divorce delegated to
her on stated conditions, and thus secure equality of divorce with
her husband. The reform suggested by the poet relating to the rule
of inheritance is based on a misunderstanding. From the inequality
of their legal shares it must not be supposed that the rule assumes
the superiority of males over females. Such an assumption would
be contrary to the spirit of Islam. The Qur«n says:
And for women are rights over men similar to those
for men over women.
The share of the daughter is determined not by any
inferiority inherent in her, but in view of her economic opportunities,
and the place she occupies in the social structure of which she
is a part and parcel. Further, according to the poets own
theory of society, the rule of inheritance must be regarded not
as an isolated factor in the distribution of wealth, but as one
factor among others working together for the same end. While the
daughter, according to Muhammadan Law, is held to be full owner
of the property given to her by both the father and the husband
at the time of her marriage; while, further, she absolutely owns
her dower-money which may be prompt or deferred according to her
own choice, and in lieu of which she can hold possession of the
whole of her husbands property till payment, the responsibility
of maintaining her throughout her life is wholly thrown on the husband.
If you judge the working of the rule of inheritance from this point
of view, you will find that there is no material difference between
the economic position of sons and daughters, and it is really by
this apparent inequality of their legal shares that the law secures
the equality demanded by the Turkish poet. The truth is that the
principles underlying the Quranic law of inheritance - this supremely
original branch of Muhammadan Law as von Kremer describes it - have
not yet received from Muslim lawyers the attention they deserve.
Modern society with its bitter class-struggles ought to set us thinking;
and if we study our laws in reference to the impending revolution
in modern economic life, we are likely to discover, in the foundational
principles, hitherto unrevealed aspects which we can work out with
a renewed faith in the wisdom of these principles.
(b) The Àadâth. The second great source
of Muhammadan Law is the traditions of the Holy Prophet. These have
been the subject of great discussion both in ancient and modern
times. Among their modern critics Professor Goldziher has subjected
them to a searching examination in the light of modern canons of
historical criticism, and arrives at the conclusion that they are,
on the whole, untrustworthy. Another European writer, after examining
the Muslim methods of determining the genuineness of a tradition,
and pointing out the theoretical possibilities of error, arrives
at the following conclusion:
It must be said in conclusion that the preceding
considerations represent only theoretical possibilities and that
the question whether and how far these possibilities have become
actualities is largely a matter of how far the actual circumstances
offered inducements for making use of the possibilities. Doubtless,
the latter, relatively speaking, were few and affected only a small
proportion of the entire Sunnah. It may therefore be said that .
. . for the most part the collections of Sunnah considered by the
Moslems as canonical are genuine records of the rise and early growth
of Islam (Mohammedan Theories of Finance).
For our present purposes, however, we must distinguish
traditions of a purely legal import from those which are of a non-legal
character. With regard to the former, there arises a very important
question as to how far they embody the pre-Islamic usages of Arabia
which were in some cases left intact, and in others modified by
the Prophet. It is difficult to make this discovery, for our early
writers do not always refer to pre-Islamic usages. Nor is it possible
to discover that usages, left intact by express or tacit approval
of the Prophet, were intended to be universal in their application.
Sh«h WalâAll«h has a very illuminating discussion
on the point. I reproduce here the substance of his view. The prophetic
method of teaching, according to Sh«h WalâAll«h,
is that, generally speaking, the law revealed by a prophet takes
especial notice of the habits, ways, and peculiarities of the people
to whom he is specifically sent. The prophet who aims at all-embracing
principles, however, can neither reveal different principles for
different peoples, nor leaves them to work out their own rules of
conduct. His method is to train one particular people, and to use
them as a nucleus for the building up of a universal Sharâah.
In doing so he accentuates the principles underlying the social
life of all mankind, and applies them to concrete cases in the light
of the specific habits of the people immediately before him. The
Sharâah values (AÁk«m) resulting from this
application (e.g. rules relating to penalties for crimes) are in
a sense specific to that people; and since their observance is not
an end in itself they cannot be strictly enforced in the case of
future generations. It was perhaps in view of this that Abë
Àanâfah, who had, a keen insight into the universal
character of Islam, made practically no use of these traditions.
The fact that he introduced the principle of IstiÁs«n,
i.e. juristic preference, which necessitates a careful study of
actual conditions in legal thinking, throws further light on the
motives which determined his attitude towards this source of Muhammadan
Law. It is said that Abë Àanâfah made no use of
traditions because there were no regular collections in his day.
In the first place, it is not true to say that there were no collections
in his day, as the collections of Abd al-M«lik and Zuhrâ
were made not less than thirty years before the death of Abë
Àanâfah. But even if we suppose that these collections
never reached him, or that they did not contain traditions of a
legal import, Abë Àanâfah, like M«lik and
AÁmad Ibn Àanbal after him, could have easily made
his own collection if he had deemed such a thing necessary. On the
whole, then, the attitude of Abë Àanâfah towards
the traditions of a purely legal import is to my mind perfectly
sound; and if modern Liberalism considers it safer not to make any
indiscriminate use of them as a source of law, it will be only following
one of the greatest exponents of Muhammadan Law in Sunni Islam.
It is, however, impossible to deny the fact that the traditionists,
by insisting on the value of the concrete case as against the tendency
to abstract thinking in law, have done the greatest service to the
Law of Islam. And a further intelligent study of the literature
of traditions, if used as indicative of the spirit in which the
Prophet himself interpreted his Revelation, may still be of great
help in understanding the life-value of the legal principles enunciated
in the Qur«n. A complete grasp of their life-value alone
can equip us in our endeavour to reinterpret the foundational principles.
(c) The Ijm«`. The third source of Muhammadan
Law is Ijm« which is, in my opinion, perhaps the most
important legal notion in Islam. It is, however, strange that this
important notion, while invoking great academic discussions in early
Islam, remained practically a mere idea, and rarely assumed the
form of a permanent institution in any Muhammadan country. Possibly
its transformation into a permanent legislative institution was
contrary to the political interests of the kind of absolute monarchy
that grew up in Islam immediately after the fourth Caliph. It was,
I think, favourable to the interest of the Umayyad and the Abbasid
Caliphs to leave the power of Ijtih«d to individual Mujtahids
rather than encourage the formation of a permanent assembly which
might become too powerful for them. It is, however, extremely satisfactory
to note that the pressure of new world-forces and the political
experience of European nations are impressing on the mind of modern
Islam the value and possibilities of the idea of Ijm«.
The growth of republican spirit and the gradual formation of legislative
assemblies in Muslim lands constitute a great step in advance. The
transfer of the power of Ijtih«d from individual representatives
of schools to a Muslim legislative assembly which, in view of the
growth of opposing sects, is the only possible form Ijm«
can take in modern times, will secure contributions to legal discussion
from laymen who happen to possess a keen insight into affairs. In
this way alone can we stir into activity the dormant spirit of life
in our legal system, and give it an evolutionary outlook. In India,
however, difficulties are likely to arise for it is doubtful whether
a non-Muslim legislative assembly can exercise the power of Ijtih«d.
But there are one or two questions which must be
raised and answered in regard to the Ijm«. Can the Ijm«
repeal the Qur«n? It is unnecessary to raise this question
before a Muslim audience, but I consider it necessary to do so in
view of a very misleading statement by a European critic in a book
called Mohammedan Theories of Finance - published by the Columbia
University. The author of this book says, without citing any authority,
that according to some Hanafâ and Mutazilah writers
the Ijm« can repeal the Qur«n. There is
not the slightest justification for such a statement in the legal
literature of Islam. Not even a tradition of the Prophet can have
any such effect. It seems to me that the author is misled by the
word Naskh in the writings of our early doctors to whom, as Im«m
Sh«Çibâë points out in al-Muwaffiq«t,
vol. iii, p. 65, this word, when used in discussions relating to
the Ijm« of the companions, meant only the power to
extend or limit the application of a Quranic rule of law, and not
the power to repeal or supersede it by another rule of law. And
even in the exercise of this power the legal theory, as Amâdâ-
a Sh«fiâ doctor of law who died about the middle
of the seventh century, and whose work is recently published in
Egypt - tells us, is that the companions must have been in possession
of a Sharâah value (Àukm) entitling them to such
a limitation or extension.
But supposing the companions have unanimously decided
a certain point, the further question is whether later generations
are bound by their decision. Shauk«nâ has fully discussed
this point, and cited the views held by writers belonging to different
schools. I think it is necessary in this connexion to discriminate
between a decision relating to a question of fact and the one relating
to a question of law. In the former case, as for instance, when
the question arose whether the two small Sërahs known as Muawwidhat«n
formed part of the Qur«n or not, and the companions
unanimously decided that they did, we are bound by their decision,
obviously because the companions alone were in a position to know
the fact. In the latter case the question is one of interpretation
only, and I venture to think, on the authority of Karkhâ,
that later generations are not bound by the decision of the companions.
Says Karkhâ: The Sunnah of the companions is binding
in matters which cannot be cleared up by Qiy«s, but it is
not so in matters which can be established by Qiy«s.
One more question may be asked as to the legislative
activity of a modern Muslim assembly which must consist, at least
for the present, mostly of men possessing no knowledge of the subtleties
of Muhammadan Law. Such an assembly may make grave mistakes in their
interpretation of law. How can we exclude or at least reduce the
possibilities of erroneous interpretation? The Persian constitution
of 1906 provided a separate ecclesiastical committee of Ulem«
- conversant with the affairs of the world - having
power to supervise the legislative activity of the Mejlis. This,
in my opinion, dangerous arrangement is probably necessary in view
of the Persian constitutional theory. According to that theory,
I believe, the king is a mere custodian of the realm which really
belongs to the Absent Im«m. The Ulem«, as representatives
of the Im«m, consider themselves entitled to supervise the
whole life of the community, though I fail to understand how, in
the absence of an apostolic succession, they establish their claim
to represent the Im«m. But whatever may be the Persian constitutional
theory, the arrangement is not free from danger, and may be tried,
if at all, only as a temporary measure in Sunnâ countries.
The Ulem« should form a vital part of a Muslim legislative
assembly helping and guiding free discussion on questions relating
to law. The only effective remedy for the possibilities of erroneous
interpretations is to reform the present system of legal education
in Muhammadan countries, to extend its sphere, and to combine it
with an intelligent study of modern jurisprudence.
(d) The Qiy«s. The fourth basis of Fiqh is
Qiy«s, i.e. the use of analogical reasoning in legislation.
In view of different social and agricultural conditions prevailing
in the countries conquered by Islam, the school of Abë Àanâfah
seem to have found, on the whole, little or no guidance from the
precedents recorded in the literature of traditions. The only alternative
open to them was to resort to speculative reason in their interpretations.
The application of Aristotelian logic, however, though suggested
by the discovery of new conditions in Iraq, was likely to prove
exceedingly harmful in the preliminary stages of legal development.
The intricate behaviour of life cannot be subjected to hard and
fast rules logically deducible from certain general notions. Yet,
looked at through the spectacles of Aristotles logic, it appears
to be a mechanism pure and simple with no internal principle of
movement. Thus, the school of Abë Àanâfah tended
to ignore the creative freedom and arbitrariness of life, and hoped
to build a logically perfect legal system on the lines of pure reason.
The legists of Àij«z, however, true to the practical
genius of their race, raised strong protests against the scholastic
subtleties of the legalists of Iraq, and their tendency to imagine
unreal cases which they rightly thought would turn the Law of Islam
into a kind of lifeless mechanism. These bitter controversies among
the early doctors of Islam led to a critical definition of the limitations,
conditions, and correctives of Qiy«s which, though originally
appeared as a mere disguise for Mujtahids personal opinion,
eventually became a source of life and movement in the Law of Islam.
The spirit of the acute criticism of M«lik and Sh«fiâ
on Abë Àanâfahs principle of Qiy«s,
as a source of law, constitutes really an effective Semitic restraint
on the Aryan tendency to seize the abstract in preference to the
concrete, to enjoy the idea rather than the event. This was really
a controversy between the advocates of deductive and inductive methods
in legal research. The legists of Iraq originally emphasized the
eternal aspect of the notion, while those of Àij«z
laid stress on its temporal aspect. The latter, however, did not
see the full significance of their own position, and their instinctive
partiality to the legal tradition of Àij«z narrowed
their vision to the precedents that had actually happened
in the days of the Prophet and his companions. No doubt they recognized
the value of the concrete, but at the same time they eternalized
it, rarely resorting to Qiy«s based on the study of the concrete
as such. Their criticism of Abë Àanâfah and his
school, however, emancipated the concrete as it were, and brought
out the necessity of observing the actual movement and variety of
life in the interpretation of juristic principles. Thus the school
of Abë Àanâfah which fully assimilated the results
of this controversy is absolutely free in its essential principle
and possesses much greater power of creative adaptation than any
other school of Muhammadan Law. But, contrary to the spirit of his
own school, the modern Hanafâ legist has eternalized the interpretations
of the founder or his immediate followers much in the same way as
the early critics of Abë Àanâfah eternalized the
decisions given on concrete cases. Properly understood and applied,
the essential principle of this school, i.e. Qiy«s, as Sh«fiâ
rightly says, is only another name for Ijtih«d which, within
the limits of the revealed texts, is absolutely free; and its importance
as a principle can be seen from the fact that, according to most
of the doctors, as Q«dâ Shauk«nâ tells us,
it was permitted even in the lifetime of the Holy Prophet.
he closing of the door of Ijtih«d is pure fiction
suggested partly by the crystallization of legal thought in Islam,
and partly by that intellectual laziness which, especially in the
period of spiritual decay, turns great thinkers into idols. If some
of the later doctors have upheld this fiction, modern Islam is not
bound by this voluntary surrender of intellectual independence.
Zarkashâ writing in the eighth century of the Hijrah rightly
observes:
If the upholders of this fiction mean that
the previous writers had more facilities, while the later writers
had more difficulties, in their way, it is, nonsense; for it does
not require much understanding to see that Ijtih«d for later
doctors is easier than for the earlier doctors. Indeed the commentaries
on the Kor«n and sunnah have been compiled and multiplied
to such an extent that the mujtahid of today has more material for
interpretation than he needs.
This brief discussion, I hope, will make it clear
to you that neither in the foundational principles nor in the structure
of our systems, as we find them today, is there anything to justify
the present attitude. Equipped with penetrative thought and fresh
experience the world of Islam should courageously proceed to the
work of reconstruction before them. This work of reconstruction,
however, has a far more serious aspect than mere adjustment to modern
conditions of life. The Great European War bringing in its wake
the awakening on Turkey - the element of stability in the world
of Islam - as a French writer has recently described her, and the
new economic experiment tried in the neighbourhood of Muslim Asia,
must open our eyes to the inner meaning and destiny of Islam. Humanity
needs three things today - a spiritual interpretation of the universe,
spiritual emancipation of the individual, and basic principles of
a universal import directing the evolution of human society on a
spiritual basis. Modern Europe has, no doubt, built idealistic systems
on these lines, but experience shows that truth revealed through
pure reason is incapable of bringing that fire of living conviction
which personal revelation alone can bring. This is the reason why
pure thought has so little influenced men, while religion has always
elevated individuals, and transformed whole societies. The idealism
of Europe never became a living factor in her life, and the result
is a perverted ego seeking itself through mutually intolerant democracies
whose sole function is to exploit the poor in the interest of the
rich. Believe me, Europe today is the greatest hindrance in the
way of mans ethical advancement. The Muslim, on the other
hand, is in possession of these ultimate ideas of the basis of a
revelation, which, speaking from the inmost depths of life, internalizes
its own apparent externality. With him the spiritual basis of life
is a matter of conviction for which even the least enlightened man
among us can easily lay down his life; and in view of the basic
idea of Islam that there can be no further revelation binding on
man, we ought to be spiritually one of the most emancipated peoples
on earth. Early Muslims emerging out of the spiritual slavery of
pre-Islamic Asia were not in a position to realize the true significance
of this basic idea. Let the Muslim of today appreciate his position,
reconstruct his social life in the light of ultimate principles,
and evolve, out of the hitherto partially revealed purpose of Islam,
that spiritual democracy which is the ultimate aim of Islam.
contents..
|