|
The Spirit of Muslim Culture
-From this summary of Ir«qâs
view you will see how a cultured Muslim Sufi`intellectually interpreted
his spiritual experience of time and space in an age which had no
idea of the theories and concepts of modern Mathematics and Physics.
Ir«qâ is really trying to reach the concept of
space as a dynamic appearance. His mind seems to be vaguely struggling
with the concept of space as an infinite continuum; yet he was unable
to see the full implications of his thought partly because he was
not a mathematician and partly because of his natural prejudice
in favour of the traditional Aristotelian idea of a fixed universe.
Again, the interpenetration of the super-spatial here
and super-eternal now in the Ultimate Reality suggests
the modern notion of space-time which Professor Alexander, in his
lectures on Space, Time, and Deity, regards as the matrix
of all things. A keener insight into the nature of time would have
led Ir«qâ to see that time is more fundamental
of the two; and that it is not a mere metaphor to say, as Professor
Alexander does say, that time is the mind of space.Ir«qâ
conceives Gods relation to the universe on the analogy of
the relation of the human soul to the body; but, instead of philosophically
reaching this position through a criticism of the spatial and temporal
aspects of experience, he simply postulates it on the basis of his
spiritual experience. It is not sufficient merely to reduce space
and time to a vanishing point-instant. The philosophical path that
leads to God as the omnipsyche of the universe lies through the
discovery of living thought as the ultimate principle of space-time.
Ir«qâs mind, no doubt, moved in the right
direction, but his Aristotelian prejudices, coupled with a lack
of psychological analysis, blocked his progress. With his view that
Divine Time is utterly devoid of change - a view obviously based
on an inadequate analysis of conscious experience - it was not possible
for him to discover the relation between Divine Time and serial
time, and to reach, through this discovery, the essentially Islamic
idea of continuous creation which means a growing universe.
Thus all lines of Muslim thought converge on a dynamic
conception of the universe. This view is further reinforced by Ibn
Maskawaihs theory of life as an evolutionary movement, and
Ibn Khaldëns view of history. History or, in the language
of the Qur«n, the days of God, is the third
source of human knowledge according to the Qur«n. It
is one of the most essential teachings of the Qur«n
that nations are collectively judged, and suffer for their misdeeds
here and now. In order to establish this proposition, the Qur«n
constantly cites historical instances, and urges upon the reader
to reflect on the past and present experience of mankind.
"Of old did We send Moses with Our signs, and
said to him: Bring forth thy people from the darkness into
the light, and remind them of the days of God." Verily, in
this are signs for every patient, grateful person.
And among those whom We had created are a people
who guide others with truth, and in accordance therewith act justly.
But as for those who treat Our signs as lies, We gradually ring
them down by means of which they know not; and though I lengthen
their days, verily, My stratagem is effectual.
Already, before your time, have precedents
been made. Traverse the Earth then, and see what hath been the end
of those who falsify the signs of God!.
If a wound hath befallen you, a wound like
it hath already befallen others; We alternate the days of successes
and reverses among peoples.
Every nation hath its fixed period.
The last verse is rather an instance of a more specific
historical generalization which, in its epigrammatic formulation,
suggests the possibility of a scientific treatment of the life of
human societies regarded as organisms. It is, therefore, a gross
error to think that the Qur«n has no germs of a historical
doctrine. The truth is that the whole spirit of the Prolegomena
of Ibn Khaldën appears to have been mainly due to the inspiration
which the author must have received from the Qur«n.
Even in his judgements of character he is, in no small degree, indebted
to the Qur«n. An instance in point is his long paragraph
devoted to an estimate of the character of the Arabs as a people.
The whole paragraph is a mere amplification of the following verses
of the Qur«n:
The Arabs of the desert are most stout in unbelief
and dissimulation; and likelier it is that they should be unaware
of the laws which God hath sent down to His Apostle; and God is
Knowing, Wise.
Of the Arabs of the desert there are some who
reckon what they expend in the cause of God as tribute, and wait
for some change of fortune to befall you: a change for evil shall
befall them! God is the Hearer, the Knower.
However, the interest of the Qur«n in
history, regarded as a source of human knowledge, extends farther
than mere indications of historical generalizations. It has given
us one of the most fundamental principles of historical criticism:
Since accuracy in recording facts which constitute the material
of history is an indispensable condition of history as a science,
and an accurate knowledge of facts ultimately depends on those who
report them, the very first principle of historical criticism is
that the reporters personal character is an important factor
in judging his testimony. The Qur«n says:
O believers! if any bad man comes to you with
a report, clear it up at once.
It is the application of the principle embodied in
this verse to the reporters of the Prophets traditions out
of which were gradually evolved the canons of historical criticism.
The growth of historical sense in Islam is a fascinating subject.
The Quranic appeal to experience, the necessity to ascertain the
exact sayings of the Prophet, and the desire to furnish permanent
sources of inspiration to posterity - all these forces contributed
to produce such men as Ibn Ish«q,ñabarâ, and
Masëdâ. But history, as an art of firing the readers
imagination, is only a stage in the development of history as a
genuine science. The possibility of a scientific treatment of history
means a wider experience, a greater maturity of practical reason,
and finally a fuller realization of certain basic ideas regarding
the nature of life and time. These ideas are in the main two; and
both form the foundation of the Quranic teaching.
1. The Unity of Human Origin. And We have created
you all from one breath of life, says the Qur«n.
But the perception of life as an organic unity is a slow achievement,
and depends for its growth on a peoples entry into the main
current of world-events. This opportunity was brought to Islam by
the rapid development of a vast empire. No doubt, Christianity,
long before Islam, brought the message of equality to mankind; but
Christian Rome did not rise to the full apprehension of the idea
of humanity as a single organism. As Flint rightly says, No
Christian writer and still less, of course, any other in the Roman
Empire, can be credited with having had more than a general and
abstract conception of human unity. And since the days of
Rome the idea does not seem to have gained much in depth and rootage
in Europe. On the other hand, the growth of territorial nationalism,
with its emphasis on what is called national characteristics, has
tended rather to kill the broad human element in the art and literature
of Europe. It was quite otherwise with Islam. Here the idea was
neither a concept of philosophy nor a dream of poetry. As a social
movement the aim of Islam was to make the idea a living factor in
the Muslims daily life, and thus silently and imperceptibly
to carry it towards fuller fruition.
2. A Keen Sense of the Reality of Time, and the Concept
of Life as a Continuous Movement in Time. It is this conception
of life and time which is the main point of interest in Ibn Khaldëns
view of history, and which justifies Flints eulogy that Plato,
Aristotle, and Augustine were not his peers, and all others were
unworthy of being even mentioned along with him. From the
remarks that I have made above I do not mean to throw doubt on the
originality of Ibn Khaldën. All that I mean to say is that,
considering the direction in which the culture of Islam had unfolded
itself, only a Muslim could have viewed history as a continuous,
collective movement, a real inevitable development in time. The
point of interest in this view of history is the way in which Ibn
Khaldën conceives the process of change. His conception is
of infinite importance because of the implication that history,
as a continuous movement in time, is a genuinely creative movement
and not a movement whose path is already determined. Ibn Khaldën
was not a metaphysician. Indeed he was hostile to Metaphysics. But
in view of the nature of his conception of time he may fairly be
regarded as a forerunner of Bergson. I have already discussed the
intellectual antecedents of this conception in the cultural history
of Islam. The Quranic view of the alternation of day and night
as a symbol of the Ultimate Reality which appears in a fresh
glory every moment, the tendency in Muslim Metaphysics to
regard time as objective, Ibn Maskawaihs view of life as an
evolutionary movement, and lastly al-Bârënâs
definite approach to the conception of Nature as a process of becoming
- all this constituted the intellectual inheritance of Ibn Khaldën.
His chief merit lies in his acute perception of, and systematic
expression to, the spirit of the cultural movement of which he was
a most brilliant product. In the work of this genius the anti-classical
spirit of the Qur«n scores its final victory over Greek
thought; for with the Greeks time was either unreal, as in Plato
and Zeno, or moved in a circle, as in Heraclitus and the Stoics.
Whatever may be the criterion by which to judge the forward steps
of a creative movement, the movement itself, if conceived as cyclic,
ceases to be creative. Eternal recurrence is not eternal creation;
it is eternal repetition.
We are now in a position to see the true significance
of the intellectual revolt of Islam against Greek philosophy. The
fact that this revolt originated in a purely theological interest
shows that the anti-classical spirit of the Qur«n asserted
itself in spite of those who began with a desire to interpret Islam
in the light of Greek thought.
It now remains to eradicate a grave misunderstanding
created by Spenglers widely read book, The Decline of the
West. His two chapters devoted to the problem of Arabian culture
constitute a most important contribution to the cultural history
of Asia. They are, however, based on a complete misconception of
the nature of Islam as a religious movement, and of the cultural
activity which it initiated. Spenglers main thesis is that
each culture is a specific organism, having no point of contact
with cultures that historically precede or follow it. Indeed, according
to him, each culture has its own peculiar way of looking at things
which is entirely inaccessible to men belonging to a different culture.
In his anxiety to prove this thesis he marshals an overwhelming
array of facts and interpretations to show that the spirit of European
culture is through and through anti-classical. And this anti-classical
spirit of European culture is entirely due to the specific genius
of Europe, and not to any inspiration she may have received from
the culture of Islam which, according to Spengler, is thoroughly
Magian in spirit and character. Spenglers view
of the spirit of modern culture is, in my opinion, perfectly correct.
I have, however, tried to show in these lectures that the anti-classical
spirit of the modern world has really arisen out of the revolt of
Islam against Greek thought. It is obvious that such a view cannot
be acceptable to Spengler; for, if it is possible to show that the
anti-classical spirit of modern culture is due to the inspiration
which it received from the culture immediately preceding it, the
whole argument of Spengler regarding the complete mutual independence
of cultural growths would collapse. I am afraid Spenglers
anxiety to establish this thesis has completely perverted his vision
of Islam as a cultural movement.
By the expression Magian culture Spengler
means the common culture associated with what he calls Magian
group of religions, i.e. Judaism, ancient Chaldean religion,
early Christianity, Zoroastrianism, and Islam. That a Magian crust
has grown over Islam, I do not deny. Indeed my main purpose in these
lectures has been to secure a vision of the spirit of Islam as emancipated
from its Magian overlayings which, in my opinion, have misled Spengler.
His ignorance of Muslim thought on the problem of time, as well
as of the way in which the I, as a free centre of experience,
has found expression in the religious experience of Islam, is simply
appalling. Instead of seeking light from the history of Muslim thought
and experience, he prefers to base his judgement on vulgar beliefs
as to the beginning and end of time. Just imagine a man of overwhelming
learning finding support for the supposed fatalism of Islam in such
Eastern expressions and proverbs as the vault of time,
and everything has a time! However, on the origin and
growth of the concept of time in Islam, and on the human ego as
a free power, I have said enough in these lectures. It is obvious
that a full examination of Spenglers view of Islam, and of
the culture that grew out of it, will require a whole volume. In
addition to what I have said before, I shall offer here one more
observation of a general nature.
The kernel of the prophetic teaching,
says Spengler, is already Magian. There is one God - be He
called Yahweh, Ahuramazda, or Marduk-Baal - who is the principle
of good, and all other deities are either impotent or evil. To this
doctrine there attached itself the hope of a Messiah, very clear
in Isaiah, but also bursting out everywhere during the next centuries,
under pressure of an inner necessity. It is the basic idea of Magian
religion, for it contains implicitly the conception of the world-historical
struggle between Good and Evil, with the power of Evil prevailing
in the middle period, and the Good finally triumphant on the Day
of Judgement.60 If this view of the prophetic teaching is
meant to apply to Islam it is obviously a misrepresentation. The
point to note is that the Magian admitted the existence of false
gods; only they did not turn to worship them. Islam denies the very
existence of false gods. In this connexion Spengler fails to appreciate
the cultural value of the idea of the finality of prophethood in
Islam. No doubt, one important feature of Magian culture is a perpetual
attitude of expectation, a constant looking forward to the coming
of Zoroasters unborn sons, the Messiah, or the Paraclete of
the fourth gospel. I have already indicated the direction in which
the student of Islam should seek the cultural meaning of the doctrine
of finality in Islam. It may further be regarded as a psychological
cure for the Magian attitude of constant expectation which tends
to give a false view of history. Ibn Khaldën, seeing the spirit
of his own view of history, has fully criticized and, I believe,
finally demolished the alleged revelational basis in Islam of an
idea similar, at least in its psychological effects, to the original
Magian idea which had reappeared in Islam under the pressure of
Magian thought.
contents..
|