|
The Conception of God and the Meaning of Prayer
-The word knowledge, as applied
to the finite ego, always means discursive knowledge - a temporal
process which moves round a veritable other, supposed
to exist per se and confronting the knowing ego. In this sense knowledge,
even if we extend it to the point of omniscience, must always remain
relative to its confronting other, and cannot, therefore,
be predicated of the Ultimate Ego who, being all-inclusive, cannot
be conceived as having a perspective like the finite ego. The universe,
as we have seen before, is not an other existing per
se in opposition to God. It is only when we look at the act of creation
as a specific event in the life-history of God that the universe
appears as an independent other. From the standpoint
of the all-inclusive Ego there is no other. In Him thought
and deed, the act of knowing and the act of creating, are identical.
It may be argued that the ego, whether finite or infinite, is inconceivable
without a confronting non-ego, and if there is nothing outside the
Ultimate Ego, the Ultimate Ego cannot be conceived as an ego. The
answer to this argument is that logical negations are of no use
in forming a positive concept which must be based on the character
of Reality as revealed in experience. Our criticism of experience
reveals the Ultimate Reality to be a rationally directed life which,
in view of our experience of life, cannot be conceived except as
an organic whole, a something closely knit together and possessing
a central point of reference. This being the character of life,
the ultimate life can be conceived only as an ego. Knowledge, in
the sense of discursive knowledge, however infinite, cannot, therefore,
be predicated of an ego who knows, and, at the same time, forms
the ground of the object known. Unfortunately, language does not
help us here.
We possess no word to express the kind of knowledge which is also
creative of its object. The alternative concept of Divine knowledge
is omniscience in the sense of a single indivisible act of perception
which makes God immediately aware of the entire sweep of history,
regarded as an order of specific events, in an eternal now.
This is how Jal«luddân Daw«nâ, Ir«qâ,
and Professor Royce in our own times conceived Gods knowledge.
There is an element of truth in this conception. But it suggests
a closed universe, a fixed futurity, a predetermined, unalterable
order of specific events which, like a superior fate, has once for
all determined the directions of Gods creative activity. In
fact, Divine knowledge regarded as a kind of passive omniscience
is nothing more than the inert void of pre-Einsteinian physics,
which confers a semblance of unity on things by holding them together,
a sort of mirror passively reflecting the details of an already
finished structure of things which the finite consciousness reflects
in fragments only. Divine knowledge must be conceived as a living
creative activity to which the objects that appear to exist in their
own right are organically related. By conceiving Gods knowledge
as a kind of reflecting mirror, we no doubt save His fore-knowledge
of future events; but it is obvious that we do so at the expense
of His freedom. The future certainly pre-exists in the organic whole
of Gods creative life, but it pre-exists as an open possibility,
not as a fixed order of events with definite outlines. An illustration
will perhaps help us in understanding what I mean. Suppose, as sometimes
happens in the history of human thought, a fruitful idea with a
great inner wealth of applications emerges into the light of your
consciousness.
You are immediately aware of the idea as a complex whole; but the
intellectual working out of its numerous bearings is a matter of
time. Intuitively all the possibilities of the idea are present
in your mind. If a specific possibility, as such, is not intellectually
known to you at a certain moment of time, it is not because your
knowledge is defective, but because there is yet no possibility
to become known. The idea reveals the possibilities of its application
with advancing experience, and sometimes it takes more than one
generation of thinkers before these possibilities are exhausted.
Nor is it possible, on the view of Divine knowledge as a kind of
passive omniscience, to reach the idea of a creator. If history
is regarded merely as a gradually revealed photo of a predetermined
order of events, then there is no room in it for novelty and initiation.
Consequently, we can attach no meaning to the word creation,
which has a meaning for us only in view of our own capacity for
original action. The truth is that the whole theological controversy
relating to predestination is due to pure speculation with no eye
on the spontaneity of life, which is a fact of actual experience.
No doubt, the emergence of egos endowed with the power of spontaneous
and hence unforeseeable action is, in a sense, a limitation on the
freedom of the all-inclusive Ego. But this limitation is not externally
imposed. It is born out of His own creative freedom whereby He has
chosen finite egos to be participators of His life, power, and freedom.
But how, it may be asked, is it possible to reconcile
limitation with Omnipotence? The word limitation need
not frighten us. The Qur«n has no liking for abstract
universals. It always fixes its gaze on the concrete which the theory
of Relativity has only recently taught modern philosophy to see.
All activity, creational or otherwise, is a kind of limitation without
which it is impossible to conceive God as a concrete operative Ego.
Omnipotence, abstractly conceived, is merely a blind, capricious
power without limits. The Qur«n has a clear and definite
conception of Nature as a cosmos of mutually related forces. It,
therefore, views Divine omnipotence as intimately related to Divine
wisdom, and finds the infinite power of God revealed, not in the
arbitrary and the capricious, but in the recurrent, the regular,
and the orderly. At the same time, the Qur«n conceives
God as holding all goodness in His hands. If, then,
the rationally directed Divine will is good, a very serious problem
arises. The course of evolution, as revealed by modern science,
involves almost universal suffering and wrongdoing. No doubt, wrongdoing
is confined to man only. But the fact of pain is almost universal,
thought it is equally true that men can suffer and have suffered
the most excruciating pain for the sake of what they have believed
to be good. Thus the two facts of moral and physical evil stand
out prominent in the life of Nature. Nor can the relativity of evil
and the presence of forces that tend to transmute it be a source
of consolation to us; for, in spite of all this relativity and transmutation,
there is something terribly positive about it. How is it, then,
possible to reconcile the goodness and omnipotence of God with the
immense volume of evil in His creation? This painful problem is
really the crux of Theism. No modern writer has put it more accurately
than Naumann in his Briefe Ü ber Religion. We possess,
he says:
a knowledge of the world which teaches us a
God of power and strength, who sends out life and death as simultaneously
as shadow and light, and a revelation, a faith as to salvation which
declares the same God to be father. The following of the world-God
produces the morality of the struggle for existence, and the service
of the Father of Jesus Christ produces the morality of compassion.
And yet they are not two gods, but one God. Somehow or other, their
arms intertwine. Only no mortal can say where and how this occurs.
To the optimist Browning all is well with the world;
to the pessimist Schopenhauer the world is one perpetual winter
wherein a blind will expresses itself in an infinite variety of
living things which bemoan their emergence for a moment and then
disappear for ever. The issue thus raised between optimism and pessimism
cannot be finally decided at the present stage of our knowledge
of the universe. Our intellectual constitution is such that we can
take only a piecemeal view of things. We cannot understand the full
import of the great cosmic forces which work havoc, and at the same
time sustain and amplify life. The teaching of the Qur«n,
which believes in the possibility of improvement in the behaviour
of man and his control over natural forces, is neither optimism
nor pessimism. It is meliorism, which recognizes a growing universe
and is animated by the hope of mans eventual victory over
evil.
But the clue to a better understanding of our difficulty
is given in the legend relating to what is called the Fall of Man.
In this legend the Qur«n partly retains the ancient
symbols, but the legend is materially transformed with a view to
put an entirely fresh meaning into it. The Quranic method of complete
or partial transformation of legends in order to besoul them with
new ideas, and thus to adapt them to the advancing spirit of time,
is an important point which has nearly always been overlooked both
by Muslim and non-Muslim students of Islam. The object of the Qur«n
in dealing with these legends is seldom historical; it nearly always
aims at giving them a universal moral or philosophical import. And
it achieves this object by omitting the names of persons and localities
which tend to limit the meaning of a legend by giving it the colour
of a specific historical event, and also by deleting details which
appear to belong to a different order of feeling. This is not an
uncommon method of dealing with legends. It is common in non-religious
literature. An instance in point is the legend of Faust, to which
the touch of Goethes genius has given a wholly new meaning.
Turning to the legend of the Fall we find it in a
variety of forms in the literatures of the ancient world. It is,
indeed, impossible to demarcate the stages of its growth, and to
set out clearly the various human motives which must have worked
in its slow transformation. But confining ourselves to the Semitic
form of the myth, it is highly probable that it arose out of the
primitive mans desire to explain to himself the infinite misery
of his plight in an uncongenial environment, which abounded in disease
and death and obstructed him on all sides in his endeavour to maintain
himself. Having no control over the forces of Nature, a pessimistic
view of life was perfectly natural to him. Thus, in an old Babylonian
inscription, we find the serpent (phallic symbol), the tree, and
the woman offering an apple (symbol of virginity) to the man. The
meaning of the myth is clear - the fall of man from a supposed state
of bliss was due to the original sexual act of the human pair. The
way in which the Qur«n handles this legend becomes clear
when we compare it with the narration of the Book of Genesis. The
remarkable points of difference between the Quranic and the Biblical
narrations suggest unmistakably the purpose of the Quranic narration.
1. The Qur«n omits the serpent and the
rib-story altogether. The former omission is obviously meant to
free the story from its phallic setting and its original suggestion
of a pessimistic view of life. The latter omission is meant to suggest
that the purpose of the Quranic narration is not historical, as
in the case of the Old Testament, which gives us an account of the
origin of the first human pair by way of a prelude to the history
of Israel. Indeed, in the verses which deal with the origin of man
as a living being, the Qur«n uses the words Bashar or
Ins«n, not ÿdam, which it reserves for man in his capacity
of Gods vicegerent on earth. The purpose of the Qur«n
is further secured by the omission of proper names mentioned in
the Biblical narration - Adam and Eve. The word Adam is retained
and used more as a concept than as the name of a concrete human
individual. This use of the word is not without authority in the
Qur«n itself. The following verse is clear on the point:
"We created you; then fashioned you; then
said We to the angels, "prostrate yourself unto Adam").
2. The Qur«n splits up the legend into
two distinct episodes the one relating to what it describes
simply as the tree and the other relating to the tree
of eternity and the kingdom that faileth not.
The first episode is mentioned in the 7th and the second in the
20th Sërah of the Qur«n. According to the Qur«n,
Adam and his wife, led astray by Satan whose function is to create
doubts in the minds of men, tasted the fruit of both the trees,
whereas according to the Old Testament man was driven out of the
Garden of Eden immediately after his first act of disobedience,
and God placed, at the eastern side of the garden, angels and a
flaming sword, turning on all sides, to keep the way to the tree
of life.
3. The Old Testament curses the earth for Adams
act of disobedience; the Qur«n declares the earth to
be the dwelling place of man and a source of profit
to him for the possession of which he ought to be grateful to God.
And We have established you on the earth and given you therein
the supports of life. How little do ye give thanks! (7:10).
Nor is there any reason to suppose that the word Jannat (Garden)
as used here means the supersensual paradise from which man is supposed
to have fallen on this earth. According to the Qur«n,
man is not a stranger on this earth. And We have caused you
to grow from the earth, says the Qur«n. The Jannat,
mentioned in the legend, cannot mean the eternal abode of the righteous.
In the sense of the eternal abode of the righteous, Jannat is described
by the Qur«n to be the place wherein the righteous
will pass to one another the cup which shall engender no light discourse,
no motive to sin. It is further described to be the place
wherein no weariness shall reach the righteous, nor forth
from it shall they be cast. In the Jannat mentioned in the
legend, however, the very first event that took place was mans
sin of disobedience followed by his expulsion. In fact, the Qur«n
itself explains the meaning of the word as used in its own narration.
In the second episode of the legend the garden is described as a
place where there is neither hunger, nor thirst, neither heat
nor nakedness. I am, therefore, inclined to think that the
Jannat in the Quranic narration is the conception of a primitive
state in which man is practically unrelated to his environment and
consequently does not feel the sting of human wants the birth of
which alone marks the beginning of human culture.
Thus we see that the Quranic legend of the Fall has
nothing to do with the first appearance of man on this planet. Its
purpose is rather to indicate mans rise from a primitive state
of instinctive appetite to the conscious possession of a free self,
capable of doubt and disobedience. The Fall does not mean any moral
depravity; it is mans transition from simple consciousness
to the first flash of self-consciousness, a kind of waking from
the dream of nature with a throb of personal causality in ones
own being. Nor does the Qur«n regard the earth as a
torture-hall where an elementally wicked humanity is imprisoned
for an original act of sin. Mans first act of disobedience
was also his first act of free choice; and that is why, according
to the Quranic narration, Adams first transgression was forgiven.
Now goodness is not a matter of compulsion; it is the selfs
free surrender to the moral ideal and arises out of a willing co-operation
of free egos. A being whose movements are wholly determined like
a machine cannot produce goodness. Freedom is thus a condition of
goodness. But to permit the emergence of a finite ego who has the
power to choose, after considering the relative values of several
courses of action open to him, is really to take a great risk; for
the freedom to choose good involves also the freedom to choose what
is the opposite of good. That God has taken this risk shows His
immense faith in man; it is for man now to justify this faith. Perhaps
such a risk alone makes it possible to test and develop the potentialities
of a being who was created of the goodliest fabric and
then brought down to be the lowest of the low. As the
Qur«n says: And for trial will We test you with
evil and with good (21:35). Good and evil, therefore, though
opposites, must fall within the same whole. There is no such thing
as an isolated fact; for facts are systematic wholes the elements
of which must be understood by mutual reference. Logical judgement
separates the elements of a fact only to reveal their interdependence.
continued..
|