Religious Diversity and Social Unity*
Dr. Rowan Williams
Abstract
If you believe what some commentators have to say, one
of the major factors provoking conflict in our world is the sheer fact
of different religious convictions: in our own Country, it seems to be
assumed by many that if we could only get the relation between ‘faith
communities’ right, social harmony would inevitably follow. And
conversely, any expression of a belief that one’s own religious loyalty
is absolute, any statement of the belief that I, as a Christian or a
Muslim or a Buddhist or whatever, am speaking the truth, is regarded as
threatening and unacceptable. Surely the problem lies with this contest
over the truth; surely, if religious people would stop speaking about
truth and acknowledge that they were only expressing opinions and
conditional loyalties, we should be spared the risk of continuing social
conflict and even violence.
But what this hopeful fantasy conceals is an assumption that talking
about truth is always less important than talking about social harmony;
and, since social harmony doesn’t seem to have any universal self
evident definition, it is bound to be defined by those who happen to
hold power at any given time which, uncomfortably, implies that power
itself is more important than truth. To be concerned about truth is at
least to recognise that there are things about humanity and the world
that cannot be destroyed by oppression and injustice that no power can
dismantle. The cost of giving up talking of truth is high: it means
admitting that power has the last word. And ever since Plato’s
Republic political thinkers have sought to avoid this conclusion,
because it means that there is no significance at all in the witness of
someone who stands against the powers that prevail at any given time;
somehow, political philosophy needs to give an account of suffering for
the sake of conscience, and without a notion of truth that is more than
simply a list of the various things people prefer to believe, no such
account can be given.
So the fact of disagreement between religious communities is in fact
crucially important for the health of our common human life. Because
these communities will not readily give up their claims to truth in
response to the appeal from the powers of the world around to be at one
for the sake of social harmony, they testify that power, even when it is
apparently working for the good of a majority, cannot guarantee that
certain values and visions will remain, whatever may happen. But does
this concern for truth mean that there is always going to be damaging
conflict wherever there is religious diversity? What about the cost of
religious diversity to ‘social cohesion’– to use the word that is
currently popular in British political rhetoric? Does disagreement about
truth necessarily mean the violent disruption of social cooperation? I
shall be arguing that it does not, and that, on the contrary, a robust
view of disagreement and debate between religious communities may
(unexpectedly?) playa major role in securing certain kinds of social
unity or cohesion.
The first point I want to make is about the very nature of religious
language. To believe in an absolute religious truth is to believe that
the object of my belief is not vulnerable to the contingencies of human
history: God’s mind and character cannot be changed by what happens here
in the world. And the logic of this is that an apparent defeat in the
world for my belief cannot be the end of the story; God does
not fail because I fail to persuade others or because my community fails
to win some kind of power. Now if I believe for a moment that my failure
or our failure is a failure or defeat for God, then my temptation will
be to seek for any means possible to avoid such an outcome; and that way
lies terrorism and religious war and persecution. The idea that any
action, however extreme or disruptive or even murderous, is justified if
it averts failure or defeat for my belief is not really consistent with
the conviction that my failure is not God’s. Indeed, it reveals a
fundamental lack of conviction in the eternity and sufficiency of the
object of faith. In plain English, religious violence suggests religious
insecurity. When different communities have the same sort of conviction
of the absolute truth of their perspective, there is certainly an
intellectual and spiritual challenge to be met; but the logic of belief
ought to make it plain that there is no defence for the sort of violent
contest in which any means, however inhuman, can be justified by appeal
to divine sanction. The divine cannot need protection by human violence.
It is a point uniquely captured in the words of Jesus before the Roman
governor: ‘My kingdom is not of this world. If it were, my servants
would fight’ (In 19.36).
So the rather paradoxical conclusion appears that the more religious
people are utterly serious about the truth of their convictions, the
less they will sanction all out violence; they will have a trust that
what truly is will remain, whatever the vicissitudes of society
and history. And they will be aware that compelling religious allegiance
by violence is tantamount to replacing divine power with human; hence
the Qur’anic insistence that there can be no compulsion in matters of
religious faith. It is crucial to faith in a really existing and
absolute transcendent agency that it should be understood to be what it
is independently of any lesser power: the most disturbing form of
secularisation is when this is forgotten or misunderstood. And the
difficult fact is that it has been so forgotten or misunderstood in so
many contexts over the millennia. It has regularly been confused with
cultural or national integrity, with structures of social control, with
class and regional identities, with empire; and it has been imposed in
the interest of all these and other forms of power. Despite Jesus’ words
in John’s gospel, Christianity has been promoted and defended
at the point of the sword and legally supported by extreme sanctions;
despite the Qur’anic axiom, Islam has been supported in the same way,
with extreme penalties for abandoning it and civil disabilities for
those outside the faith. There is no religious tradition whose history
is exempt from such temptation and such failure
Like others, I have sometimes been very critical of the heritage of the
European Enlightenment where it has been used to appeal to timeless and
obvious rational truths which are superior to the truths claimed for
revelation and imparted in the historical processes of communal life.
But it should be granted that the Enlightenment had a major role in
highlighting some of the inner contradictions of religious language and
behaviour in the wake of an age when so much violence had been justified
by the rhetoric of faith. After the wars of religion in Europe, it was
plausible and important to challenge those habits of thought which had
made it seem natural to plunge whole societies– indeed, the greater part
of a whole continent– into murderous chaos on the pretext of religious
dispute. For the major thinkers of the Enlightenment, the contrast was
between absolutes that could be defended only on the basis of arbitrary
religious authority and absolutes that were established by universal
reason; and it was obvious that the latter promised peace because they
did not need any reference to authorities that, in the nature of the
case, could be accepted only by certain groups. By forcing religious
authorities to acknowledge that they could not have the legal and civic
right to demand submission, Enlightenment thinkers in a sense obliged
believers to accept what was in fact an implication of their own
religious faith that power in this worldly terms was an inappropriate
vehicle for faith.
But the enlightenment dream of a universal rationality proved in the
event as vulnerable and questionable as any religious project. It became
entangled in theories and discourses of racial superiority (supported by
a particular reading of evolutionary biology) and the economic
determinism of capitalist theory and practice; it developed a complex
and unhealthy relationship with nationalism, which was, increasingly,
seen as the practical vehicle for emancipation and rationalisation; and
its own account of universal reason was (as I noted in a lecture here in
Singapore some months ago) undermined first by Marxian and Freudian
theories, then by the structuralist and postmodemist revolutions.
European rationality– and its American manifestations in the Declaration
of Independence and the political philosophy flowing from that– came to
seem as local and arbitrary as any other creed; in the world of global
politics, it depended on force as much as argument. And if you come to
believe that the values of a certain culture– whether Western democracy
or any other– are absolute and impossible for rational people to argue
about, then, when some groups resist or disagree, you have a theory that
licenses to suppress them; what is more, because you have no
transcendent foundation for holding to these values, you may come to
believe that any and all methods are justified in promoting or defending
them, since they will not necessarily survive your failure or
defeat.
Thus the Enlightenment hope of universal harmony on the grounds of
reason can become a sophisticated version of the priority of force over
everything else, a journey back towards the position that Plato exerted
all his energy to refute in the Republic. If the power of
argument proves not be universal after all, sooner or later we are back
with coercion; and when that happens it becomes harder and harder to
hold firm to the classical liberal principles that are at the heart of
the Enlightenment vision, harder and harder– for example– to maintain
that torture or the deliberate killing of the innocent in order to
protect the values of society can never in any circumstances be right.
It is one of the great moral conundrums posed by the experience of
recent years: what if the preserving of civil liberties and the
preserving of the security of a liberal society turn out not always to
be compatible?
The reality of religious plurality in a society declares, as we have
already seen, that some human groups hold to their convictions with an
absolute loyalty, believing they are true and thus non negotiable. If
they thought otherwise about these convictions, they might be involved
in negotiations about merging or uniting in some way; there would be no
ground for holding on to a distinct identity. Yet they do hold to their
claims to truthfulness, and so declare to the society around that
certain things are not liable to be changed simply because of to changes
in fashion or political theory or political convenience. The lasting
plurality of religious convictions is itself a mark of the seriousness
of the convictions involved. Some things are too important to
compromise. But if a religious community is as serious as it
ought to be about its beliefs, this refusal to compromise is accompanied
by the confidence that, whether or not these particular beliefs prevail
in any society, they will still be true, and that therefore we do not
have to be consumed with anxiety about their survival. The religious
witness is able to confront possible political failure, even social
collapse, in the trust that all is not and cannot be lost, even when the
future becomes unimaginably dark; what it will not do is to sanction any
policy of survival at all costs (including the cost of basic humane
conventions and moral boundaries).
Thus my first point about the role of plural religious communities in
society is that they both underpin the notion that there are values
which are not negotiable, and that at the same time they prohibit any
conclusion that such values can ultimately be defended by violence. They
challenge the drift from Enlightenment optimism to the postmodern
enthronement of power and interest as the sole elements in political
life; that is, they allow societies as well as person to fail with grace
and to find space beyond anxiety. That is not at all the same as saying
that they require passivity, resignation to the unprincipled power of
others. But they allow human beings the dignity of accepting defeat in
certain circumstances where the alternative is to abandon the moral
essence of a society in order to win: they suggest the subversive but
all important insight that failure might be preferable to victory at the
cost of tolerating, say, torture or random military reprisal as normal
elements in political life. By being absolute and thus in a sense
irreconcilable, they remind society that a unity imposed by force will
always undermine the moral substance of social and political life. There
is no way of finding a position outside or beyond diverse faith
traditions from which to broker a union between them in which their
convictions can be reconciled; and this is not bad news but good– good
because it does two things at once. It affirms transcendent values; and
by insisting that no other values are absolute, it denies to any
other system of values any justification for uncontrolled violence.
Transcendent values can be defended through violence only by those who
do not fully understand their transcendent character; and if no other
value is absolute, no other value can claim the right to unconditional
defense by any means and at all costs. Thus the rationally
irreconcilable systems of religious belief rule out any assumption that
coercive power is the last resort or the ultimate authority in our
world.
And if that is the case, we can see how religious plurality may serve
the cause of social unity, paradoxically but genuinely. If we are
prohibited from claiming that social harmony can be established by
uncontrolled coercive power– that is, if we are obliged to make a case
for the legitimacy of any social order– but are also prohibited
from solving the problem by a simple appeal to universal reason, we are
left with a model of politics which is always to do with negotiation and
the struggle for mutual understanding. Politics is clearly identified as
something pragmatic and ‘secular’, in the sense that it is not about
absolutes. As the world now is, diverse religious traditions very
frequently inhabit one territory, one nation, one social unit (and that
may be a relatively small unit like a school, or a housing cooperative
or even a business). And in such a setting, we cannot avoid the
pragmatic and secular question of’ common security’: what is needed for
our convictions to flourish is bound up with what is needed for the
convictions of other groups to flourish. We learn that we can best
defend ourselves by defending others. In a plural society, Christians
secure their religious liberty by advocacy for the liberty of Muslims or
Jews to have the same right to be heard in the continuing conversation
about the direction and ethos of a society that is characteristic of
liberal polity in the broadest sense of the word.
Diverse religious communities thus approach each other in these social
units with a powerful interest in finding what sort of values and
priorities can claim the widest ‘ownership’. This is not an effort to
discover the principles of a generalised global ethic to which different
traditions can sign up, tempting as this vision is; the work is more
piecemeal and less concerned with programmatic agreed statements though
it is certainly a significant moment when diverse communities can take
responsibility for common declarations of some kind. The Alexandria
Declaration was one such, laying down the limits of what could be
defended in the name of religion within the conflicts of the Holy Land;
in the same context, more recently, the declaration made by the Chief
Rabbis of Israel and the representatives of the Church of England in
October of this year outlined the protocols which both sides believed to
be essential in defending each other– and other religious bodies–
against physical attack or malicious misrepresentation. It is highly
desirable that communities of faith continue to work at joint statements
of witness about the environmental crisis (still an area that needs far
more interfaith collaboration). And the levels of joint witness over
matters around bioethics, for example, are significant wherever a
narrowly and aggressively non religious rationality presses for certain
kinds of change. At the same time, where each community recognises that
no one religious tradition can claim to control the processes of public
life, this may bring a realism about what the state can and cannot be
expected to take for granted and thus a willingness to find, once again,
strategies that can win maximal rather than ideal levels of ownership.
A certain pragmatism about what can be agreed as common moral ‘property’
combined with a strong advocacy of each community’s freedom both to
practise its faith and to express and argue it in public– this is what
religious plurality in a contemporary society may look like. It suggests
and helps to secure a state of affairs in which the definition of public
policy is never carried through in abstraction from the variety of
actual convictions that is evidenced in society– not because anyone of
these asserts its right to dictate, but because all claim the freedom to
join in public argument in ways that insist on the need for what I have
been calling maximal ownership. So, if a society seeks to legislate for
euthanasia, for the absolute equivalence of marriage and any other kind
of partnership, for discrimination against minorities in the name of
social cohesion, religious bodies may be expected to argue, not for
their right to settle the matter, but for a settlement that manifestly
respects their conviction to the extent that they can defend it as
legitimate even if not ideal. The notion that social unity can be
secured by a policy of marginalising or ignoring communities of faith
because of their irreducible diversity rests on several errors and
fallacies, and its most serious and damaging effect is to give
credibility to the idea of a neutral and/or self evident set of secular
principles which have authority to override the particular convictions
of religious groups. And, as 1 have argued at length in other places,
this amounts to the requirement that religious believers leave their
most strongly held and distinctive principles at the door when they
engage in public argument: not a good recipe for lasting social unity.
Religious diversity in the modern state can thus be seen as a standing
obstacle to any enshrining of a state absolutism (even a purportedly
liberal variety) in ways that could pretend to legitimise coercion in
the name of (non–religious) values; and it can be seen as a guarantor of
the fullest argument and consultation in a democratic society, insisting
that communities of faith have a stake in the decisions of the state and
its moral direction. This last is important not only in the largely
negative instances I have quoted but also in the pressure that
communities of faith can bring to bear in order to persuade the state to
act beyond some of its normal definitions of self interest– for example
in addressing international debt and poverty, securing the best possible
deal for refugees and migrants, and setting itself some clearly moral
aims in foreign policy. This sort of thing will only happen, of course,
if religious groups can persuade an electorate to ‘own’ such a vision.
Governments in democratic societies have to be responsive to what
electorates want; and if no religious group in a religiously plural
context can insist on its preferences as of right, it is still true that
the organs of debate in democratic society allow people of faith to be
heard in pubic argument and thus to attempt persuasion.
But there is one more aspect of the plurality of religious presences
that is important for social integrity and harmony (a harmony which
includes, as mature political harmony must, the processes of honest
disagreement and negotiation). Plural religious traditions are a
reminder that for most of the human race the values of society are still
shaped by one or another history of religious belief. The narrowly
‘modern’ approach which takes it for granted that social values and
priorities are timeless turns its back on the history that forms our
convictions. All religious practice declares that we inherit
certain kinds of insight and perspective, and that to understand why we
think as we do, we need to be aware of history. So much is true of any
society in which there is a strong and visible cultural presence of
religion. But when this is a diversified presence, with distinct
convictions and practices in evidence, it turns the argument in fresh
directions. A society in which religious diversity exists is invited to
recognise that human history is not one story only; even where a
majority culture and religion exists, it is part of a wider picture. And
very frequently the engagement of different religions in dialogue and
cooperation will open up and highlight the many ways in which diverse
traditions share a heritage at various points in history. The histories
of religion intersect, in their texts and their social development and
their political encounters.
Religious diversity when studied with care and sympathy shows us a
historical world in which, whatever we say about the claims of diverse
religions to truth, there is no possibility of claiming that every human
question is answered once and for all by one system. Religions have
defined themselves in dialogue and often intellectual conflict with each
other; but that very fact implies that there will always be other ways
of posing the fundamental questions that human beings confront.
Diversity of faith points us towards a past in which there is a
kaleidoscope of human perceptions, sometimes interacting fruitfully,
sometimes in profound tension. Yet the encounter in history of these
diversities shows that diversity cannot help being interactive; and that
is in itself can prompt us to think of social unity as the process of a
constantly readjusting set of differences, not an imposed scheme
claiming totality and finality. Religious diversity becomes a stimulus
to find what it is that can be brought together in constructing a new
and more inclusive history– to find some fuller sense of the ways in
which apparently divergent strands of human thought and imagination and
faith can weave together in the formation of each other and of various
societies.
Thus in what has been historically a majority Christian culture in the
UK, the present diversity of religions within a mostly fairly secular
social environment means that the UK has had to think through its
history again in the consciousness of how it has engaged with those
others who are now on its own doorstep or within its walls which means
recognising how even a majority Christian culture has been affected by
the strand of mathematical and scientific culture stemming from the
Islamic world of the early Middle Ages and how aspects of mediaeval
Christian discourse took shape partly in reaction to Islamic thought.
The apparently alien presence of another faith has meant that we have
had to ask whether it is after a11 as completely alien as we assumed;
and as we find that it is not something from another universe, we
discover elements of language and aspiration in common. The fuller
awareness of a shared past opens up a better chance of shared future, a
home that can be built together, to borrow the compelling image used by
the British Chief Rabbi in his most recent book. Indeed Dr Sacks offers
a very helpful framework for understanding the kind of social unity I
have been imagining in this lecture. As he points out, the truth of many
contemporary societies is that there is no straightforwardly prevailing
religious position dominating society, and– with migration and growing
ethnic diversity– no ready made shared history to which everyone can
look in the same way. In such a world, a stable and robust social unity
comes from the sense of a common project which all can learn to inhabit
equally. Diverse communities resolve to enter a kind of ‘covenant’ in
which they agree on their mutual attitudes, and thus on a ‘civil’
environment, in every sense of the word; and they build on this
foundation a social order I which all have an investment. They build a
society governed by law– law as a system in which strangers can become
partners by accepting the same context of duty and entitlement in the
common project of constructing their social world.
And this happens most fruitfully, so Dr Sacks argues, when we begin from
acknowledging what he has elsewhere called ‘the dignity of difference’,
from taking seriously the experienced diversity of conviction– not from
a utopian and potentially even oppressive set of assumptions that boil
down to the belief that everyone who is ‘reasonable’ is bound tohave the
same view. Throughout this lecture I have been arguing that different
religious convictions all held in depth and with passion, give a
necessary human fullness to the moral practices of a society. They give
the resources needed to preserve the idea that some principles are non
negotiable and they also declare as plainly as possible to the society
around them that there are therefore elements of the human condition
which cannot be ignored or sidelined in the search for lasting human
welfare and justice. To extend and alter the scope of my title a little,
religious diversity tells us that the unity of actual human beings, the
integration of their experience into a meaningful whole that takes in
all aspects of their reality, is impossible without reference to the
relation of human beings to the sacred without reference to the ‘image
of God’ in Jewish and Christian terms. Any society that marginalizes
religious communities or denies them the liberty to share honestly in
public debate is fragmenting the human subject not only human society by
demanding that we ignore one overwhelming dimension of what it is to be
human.
In conclusion, then, I would maintain that the presence of diverse
religious groups in a society, allowed to have a voice in the decision
making processes of society without embarrassment, is potentially an
immense contribution to a genuinely active and interactive social
harmony and a sense of moral accountability within the social order. It
is not something to be afraid of. This argument, of course, does not
directly address the details of interfaith dialogue or its methods; but
it does suggest that when honest and careful dialogue is going on, this
will be for the ultimate good of any society. As I have said, none of
this implies for a moment that dialogue entails the compromise of
fundamental beliefs or that the issue of truth is a matter of
indifference; quite the opposite. But there is a proper kind of humility
which, even as we proclaim our conviction of truth, even as we
Christians proclaim that all human beings are called to union with God
the Father in Jesus Christ by the gift and power of the Spirit, obliges
us to acknowledge with respect the depth and richness of another’s
devotion to and obedience to what they have received as truth. As we
learn that kind of respect for each other, we remember that we have none
of us received the whole truth as God knows it; we all have
things to learn. And it is that expectant and positive attitude to our
mutual encounter that makes the relation between passionately convinced
Christians, Muslims, Jews, Hindus, Buddhists, Sikhs, whatever else,
finally a gift and not a threat to a thoroughly contemporary and plural
society and its hopes for coherence, justice and peace.
* A lecture given in
Singapore at the conclusion of the Building Bridges seminar (6th
December 2007)
|